Environmental Context

Market Based Solutions

Key Assumptions

Market-Based
Solutions

Economic Instruments
Price-Based Measures
Rights-Based Measures


Key Assumptions
Assumptions
Comparisons
Hidden Agendas


Green Consumerism
References
Site Map

 

Back to Main Menu..

Assumptions Behind Economic Instruments


Bullet pointSubstituting Money for Nature
Bullet point
Assimilative Capacity of Environ.
Bullet point
Markets More Efficient than Laws
Bullet point
Damage Caused because Env. Free
Bullet point
Economic Incentives Protect Env.

Divider

Substitutability of Money for Nature

Money collected from economic instruments is seldom used to correct environmental damage. Economists argue that if the money is spent on something equally worthwhile then the community is still no worse off; a view that those who suffer from the pollution might find hard to accept. This also assumes that the benefits that arise from the environment can be substituted for other benefits that can be bought on the market. However, environmentalists and others would counter that environmental quality is not something that can be swapped for other goods without a loss of welfare. The assumption in internalising the costs is that environmental damage can be paid for and that this is as good as, or even preferable, to avoiding the damage in the first place.

Back to Top...

Assimilative Capacity of the Environment

Some economists argue that environmental degradation occurs because of incomplete ownership of rights to use valuable environmental resources. These resources have traditionally been commonly owned by everyone (or, alternatively, owned by no-one) and open to use by anyone. These economists say there is a strong tendency for people to overexploit and degrade common property resources because of the 'tragedy of the commons' principle (Hardin 1968).

In situations where the environment cannot be privately owned, access rights or user rights can be owned. The idea of rights-based measures is to create artificial property rights and with them a market in those rights. It is argued that if people own the right to use natural resources, they will consider the longer term and manage those resources sustainably. Tradeable pollution rights are a way of allocating ownership to the assimilative capacity of the air or water through rights to pollute it.

An inherent assumption behind tradeable pollution rights and other economic instruments is that the environment can take a certain amount of pollution and that trading can ensure efficient allocation of that capacity to firms that need to utilise it. In other words, they assume that the environment has an assimilative capacity. This idea is based on the fact that some wastes, such as organic wastes that occur naturally, will decompose and break down in the environment if there are not too many of them in the one place at the one time. Other materials, such as some metals, may exist naturally in the environment at very low concentrations.

The unspoken assumption behind all such models is that the capacity of the environment to tolerate a certain number of renegades is something that we ought, collectively, take advantage of. We ought to make sure that all those slots are taken, we ought allow just as many renegades as nature itself will tolerate. (Goodin 1992, 16)

This approach is highly dependent on the ability of scientists to assess the impact of pollutants on the environment and to determine a safe level that will not irreversibly or severely damage the environment. Greenpeace campaigner Lisa Bunin argues that emissions trading puts 'blind faith' in both science and the regulatory authority's ability to set an 'acceptable' baseline air quality standard, as well as to monitor and prevent deviations at each source (Memorandum to Roger Wilson, Greenpeace, 1 July 1991).

Similarly Fowler argues that traditional approaches to regulation which set 'allowable' discharges or emissions have failed to reduce global pollution and are rapidly losing credibility. He points out that plants and animals and ecosystems interact with chemicals in such complex ways that assumptions about assimilative capacity and 'safe levels' of pollution or exposure bear little relation to reality.

Back to Top...

Environmental Damage is Caused by Failure to Price Environment

Some environmental resources; such as timber, fish and minerals; are bought and sold in the market although their price usually does not reflect the true cost of obtaining them because the damage to the environment has not been included. Other environmental resources such as clean air are not given a price at all and are therefore viewed by economists as free. Economists argue that environmental assets tend to be overused or abused because they are too cheap. Many also claim there is little incentive to protect environmental resources that are not privately owned.

Economic instruments are being advocated as a technocratic solution to environmental problems which is premised on the economist's view of the problem, that environmental degradation is caused by a failure to "value" the environment and a lack of properly defined property rights. By allowing this redefinition of the environmental problem, environmentalists and others not only forestall criticism of the market system but in fact implicitly agree that an extension of markets is the only way to solve the problem.

On the face of it the economists argument that environmental degradation is caused by a failure to value the environment is an attractive one to environmentalists. However economists take a very specific view of the term 'value' which relates it to the exchange value of a commodity whereas environmentalists have a broader concept of the word that goes far beyond economic value to incorporate aesthetic, spiritual and ethical dimensions. When economists speak of valuing the environment they mean giving it a market price based on supply and demand.

Back to Top...

Markets are More Efficient than Laws

Regulations are said to be inefficient because they require discharges from all firms to meet uniform standards regardless of their ability to meet them or alternatively require all firms to install particular pollution control technologies regardless of their ability to pay for them. Whilst this might improve environmental quality it is said to be at a high cost. Economic instruments, on the other hand, are said to permit "the burden of pollution control to be shared more efficiently among businesses" (Stavins and Whitehead 1992, 9).

The idea is that some firms can reduce their pollution more cheaply than others and that it is more efficient to expect them to reduce their pollution more than those firms for whom it would be expensive. In this way the marginal costs of pollution control, that is the additional cost of achieving an extra unit of pollution reduction, would be equalised between the businesses. For example, with an effluent charge, each firm would pay an equal rate per unit of pollution increase and those that found it cheaper to reduce their pollution than pay the charge would do so whilst those for whom pollution reduction cost more than the charge would pay the charge.

Similarly with tradeable emission permits. Those firms that could most afford to reduce their emissions could sell their excess credits to those companies least able to reduce their emissions. In both cases economists argue that a given level of air or water quality could be achieved more efficiently because the firms that could afford most to reduce their pollution levels would do so, rather than each firm reducing their pollution by the same amount. The chemical company Du Pont has estimated that its fifty-two plants achieved cost savings of over 86 per cent from the use of regional bubbles (Senecca and Taussig 1984, 232).

But often cost savings arising from economic instruments result directly from firms not having to make pollution reductions that they otherwise would have. A study by economic instrument advocates Hahn and Hester (1989, 129) found that emissions trading, although it saved money for industry by enabling firms to "avoid making emissions reductions that they otherwise would have been required to make" did not improve environmental quality.

The conflict between economic efficiency and environmental goals can be seen in the setting of baseline levels for tradeable emissions. Even proponents of trading admit that there will inevitably be a conflict and an implicit trade-off between the goals of reducing costs and improving environmental quality. They argue that the US EPA's concern with improving environmental quality has in fact hampered the effectiveness of trading and limited markets (Hahn and Hester 198, 147; Atkinson and Tietenberg 1991, 20-26).

Efficiency is often a theoretical argument rather than an empirical one. The efficiency argument assumes markets are perfectly competitive and firms have perfect information. This is not so. Jacobs (1993, 7) gives the following example;

In Britain a rise of 400% in sewerage charges failed to change firms' behaviour, even though it was shown that small investments in pollution control would pay back in under a year. The charging system was not understood by the firms affected; it was dealt with by the finance department, not the engineers; and the firms did not know the technological options available. A regulation requiring them to install the better technology would almost certainly have been more efficient&emdash;that is, cost less overall&emdash;than the huge price hike which would have been required to et the same changes made.

Savage and Hart (1993, 2) point out that; "A blinkered concern for efficiency, uses as its intellectual foundation, the fantasy world of the intermediate economics textbook: a world that is not constrained by simultaneous imperfections in the market mechanism, such as monopolies or imperfect competition, uncertainty, taxes, externalities, asymmetric information, moral hazards or incomplete markets."

It is often argued by economists that markets are more efficient than centralised government decision making because they automatically gather information and ensure that supply and demand are balanced and resources allocated efficiently. However, this sort of argument cannot be applied to artificial markets such as those created for pollution rights since the need for monitoring and enforcement remains&emdash;the regulator still needs to know what volumes and concentrations of wastes are being discharged, and needs to ensure that the firm is paying the correct amount or deserves emission credits, even when that firm is being charged for its wastes. "Any system of environmental control needs inspectors to check whether claimed emissions, discharges or resource extractions are correct: they are not less 'bureaucratic' because they are tax inspectors rather than regulatory ones" (Jacobs 1993, 7).

Emission reduction credit trades now frequently involve a broker. Brokers' fees are typically calculated as a percentage of the value of the transaction. Add to this the costs of accomplishing the air quality modelling that is frequently required for trades involving noncontiguous sources of nonuniformly mixed pollutants and the transactions costs can become very large. These costs serve to further reduce the cost savings from trades and therefore the incentive to trade, particularly when the potential savings are small. (Atkinson and Tietenberg 1991, 28)

Back to Top...

Economic Incentives Will Protect the Environment

Economists can argue that the imposed costs, even if they don't internalise the real environmental costs of polluting activity, nevertheless provide an incentive for companies to reduce their pollution and thereby save money (Jacobs 1993, 3). The contention is that legal standards might ensure firms meet particular targets but that having met them there is no incentive to go beyond them whereas with the financial incentives provided by economic instruments "businesses are constantly motivated to improve their financial performance by developing technologies that allow them to reduce their output of pollutants."(Stavins and Whitehead 1992, 30) "Properly structured economic instruments encourage industry to go beyond compliance and engage in continuous innovation and improvement." (Grabosky 1993).

The assumption here is one that rests on economic determinism; given the right economic conditions the desirable technological change will automatically occur. This view of technological development ignores the social and political factors that shape technology and which have been the basis for so much scholarship in the academic discipline of science and technology studies (MacKenzie and Wajcman 1985; Bijker, Hughes and Pinch 1987). Adding costs to a firms operations may impose pressure on it to reduce its costs but there is no guarantee that it will do so in the area where the cost is imposed (Rosenberg 1976, chapter 23). It may find it easier, cheaper, or even more profitable to apply new technology and methods in other parts of its operation or just to pass the increased cost on to the consumer, especially in oligopolistic sectors.

The degree of incentive provided will also obviously depend on how large the charge or tax or subsidy is: "if it is low, and environmental improvement is primarily achieved through major investments in plant and equipment which occur rarely, there may be little effect."(Jacobs 1993, 7) Most studies have found that in nearly all cases charges are too low to provide an incentive (OECD 1989, 114-5; Bard and Opschoor 1994, 25; Postel 1991, 32; ESD Working Groups, 1991; Stavins and Whitehead 1992, 31).

Because of the general ineffectiveness of price-based measures as incentives in practice, those promoting them tend to concentrate on their theoretical, and generally idealised, potential and compare this to the poor record of legislative instruments in practice. David James (1993) in research paper prepared for the Australian Government cites the above OECD study as evidence of the increasing use of economic instruments without mentioning the major finding of the study that they are generally ineffective as an incentive for environmentally beneficial behaviour.

In theory there is no reason why legislative instruments could not provide an incentive for ongoing improvement in performance through innovation (Cramer and Zegveld 1991; Ashford, Ayers and Stone 1985; Caldart and Ryan 1985). For example Caldart and Ryan (1985, 310) argue for regulatory approaches not to be bound by existing technologies and economic conditions so as "to encourage the type of innovation that can spur technological breakthroughs and alter economic circumstances."

The failure of legislative instruments to provide incentives has at its source the same cause as the failure of economic instruments to provide that same incentive. The power of government institutions, the will of the politicians, and the scope for public participation and scrutiny are determining factors in both cases. J. Rees (1988, 175) says of various policy instruments:

They inevitably have to operate within an institutional setting where policy goals are confused, shifting and frequently conflicting, where the implementation process does not, and cannot, operate along clear, consistent ends-means lines, and where they are prey to manipulation by interest groups within both the regulated community and the regulating authorities themselves.

Brian Wynne (1987, 4-5) makes a similar point when he points out that

implementation of standards requires an on-going interaction between competing interests such as the regulatory authority and the regulated, the nearby community and the government as well as interested parties. It generally involves adaption, compromise and negotiation.

Rees (1988, 172) says that advocates of economic mechanisms tend to assume that 'the pollution control system is populated by economically rational entrepreneurs and regulators, operating without technical, perceptual, organisational and capital availability constraints'. This is not the case. For example, a firm may not be able to afford the initial capital cost of changing production processes or putting in pre-treatment equipment, even if this would be cheaper than paying the charges in the long term.

Rees claims that a number of studies have shown that 25 to 30 per cent of dischargers who are subject to effluent charges do not understand the pricing system and that 'significantly different levels of payment could arise if they altered the strength/volume composition of the effluent'(1988, 184). Many of them do not have sufficient knowledge of alternative methods and costs to make optimal decisions in their own interest.

Tradeable pollution rights have also failed to provide the incentives hoped for. Tradeable pollution rights are supposed to provide an incentive to innovation because companies that can reduce their pollution to below baseline levels can then sell their emission credits and profit from their reduced pollution.

One of the major problems with emissions trading is setting that baseline level&emdash;the level of emissions that individual firms should have a right to attain before trading can occur. If the baseline level is too low, there will be few pollution rights for sale, because few firms will be able to reduce their pollution levels below the standards set. However, if the baseline level is too high, there will be few buyers of pollution rights because most firms will be able to meet the standards, even without innovation. In either case, there will be too little trading. In fact, although the emissions trading program was introduced in the USA in 1979, by 1989 far fewer firms than expected were banking credits or trading them with other firms.

The on-going incentive provided by tradeable pollution rights for companies to reduce their pollution only works if there are other companies wanting to increase their emissions or new companies wanting to buy credits in order to begin operations in non-attainment areas. But this means that the gains made by some firms are negated by others buying up those gains so they can put out more pollution.


Source: Sharon Beder. Charging the earth: The promotion of price-based measures for pollution control. Ecological Economics 16(1996): 51-63.

Back to Top...


© 2001 Sharon Beder