Difficult
and innaccurate
It
cannot be objective
Rational
decisions not always moral
Ignores
distributional issues
Biased
against future generations
Difficult and Innaccurate
Identifying all the consequences of a particular project or policy
option is difficult because it involves predicting the future
and dealing with the uncertain interactions between human activities
and the ecosystems in which they take place. Moreover, there will
be unintended and unexpected indirect effects arising from any
large project. While this is a problem whether one is doing a
cost&endash;benefit analysis or not, it can be crucial for the
outcome of a cost&endash;benefit analysis and could make the difference
between a project being considered to be justifiable or not.
The problem of placing a value on these consequences, once they
have been identified, was discussed in the previous section. Some
things are difficult to quantify because they are not generally
bought or sold or even paid for. These include environmental values
such as the value of clean air and water, unspoilt wilderness
areas, ecological balance and diversity. They also include social
values such as community feeling and a sense of security.
In transport, and particularly road projects, savings of time
for motorists or commuters are often the major benefit of the
project. This creates two areas of contention. One is predicting
what the time savings would be; the other is estimating what those
times savings are worth to the community.
Another aspect of cost-benefit analyses that is often not considered
is that the decision to preserve an area is reversible, whereas
the decision to develop an area may be irreversible. No allowance
is made in standard cost-benefit analysis for the importance of
keeping options open for the future.
Back to the top...
Cannot Be Objective
The Commonwealth Government (1990) recognises that different
people will put different valuations on resources and on different
ecosystems, and that these valuations can include economic, ecological,
aesthetic and ethical components. 'It is because different individuals
and groups give different weightings to these components that
conflicts of opinion arise as to how resources should be used'
(p. 4).
Some people argue that cost&endash;benefit analysis, far from
being an objective source of information, is usually used to justify
projects. In his book Technology, Environment and Human Values,
Ian Barbour argues that;
In practice, CBA is almost always a means by which an
agency justifies and promotes its own programs. The formulation
of problems and the preselection of alternatives, which are frequently
the most important decisions, occur before the analysis is made.
In the analysis itself, an agency typically overstates benefits
and understates costs. (1980, p. 170)
He argues that environmental effects and other indirect costs
tend to be neglected, whilst indirect benefits are searched for.
He goes on to say that:
While the assignment of monetary values appears to be
a technical question, it often reflects the biases of analysts
or their judgements of what the public wants. Differing weights
would be assigned by various social groups to the incommensurable
benefits of such projects. (p. 170)
Moreover, as Frank Stilwell (1986), economist at the University
of Sydney, points out, the exercise of cost&endash;benefit analysis
embodies ethical judgements about what is good for the community.
Such judgements include assumptions about whether consumer preference
reveals true environmental values. Another assumption reinforced
by cost&endash;benefit analysis is that technology is neutral
but has unintended consequences. Because cost&endash;benefit analysis
is, for reasons of practicality, only applied to total projects
rather than the design process, the idea promoted is that the
consequences of the project are inevitable &emdash;and we either
accept them with the project or reject the project. The idea of
modifying the project to prevent consequences is not encouraged
by cost&endash;benefit analysis.
Proponents of cost&endash;benefit analysis argue that, by placing
explicit values on proposed actions, the process is more open
to scrutiny by others. However, what tends to happen is that the
analysis is highly technical, and neither available nor accessible
to the public. The value judgements are hidden beneath a mass
of figures that give the impression that the analysis is rational,
neutral and objective. Barbour argues:
Value conflicts that should be resolved politically
are concluded in what look like rational, neutral, objective calculations.
This may appeal to administrators, but it hinders public debate
of the policy issues and lessens the accountability of bureaucratic
officials. Numbers carry an unwarranted authority when used to
legitimate decisions that are basically political in character
(1989, p. 170).
Public debate over the options is therefore inhibited, and public
participation is replaced by a technocratic process. Again, cost&endash;benefit
analysis may hide distributional consequences and appear neutral
when in fact a certain section of the community is benefiting.
Back to the top...
Rational Decisions Are Not Necessarily
Moral Ones
Just because the benefits of an action outweigh the costs, it
does not mean that the decision is morally correct. An individual
may not gain personally from giving money to charity but may believe
it is the right thing to do. Pearce points out that, in the same
way, 'the summation of a whole set of choices by many individuals
may give a result which the "state" or government thinks is not
right' (1983, p. 3). For example, child labour or slavery would
be considered immoral even if the economic advantages to the whole
society outweighed the costs to some individuals. Pearce argues,
that for this reason, cost&endash;benefit analysis should be seen
as an input to decision-making but should not 'supplant political
judgement'. Governments will want to know what the preferences
of individuals are but may overrule these.
In response, Stilwell (1986) points out that:
If the CBA is not decisive, then it is necessary to
determine what considerations could or should over-rule it; otherwise
its claimed advantages in terms of making the decision-making
processes more systematic and consistent tend to evaporate. (p.
25)
Others argue that cost&endash;benefit analysis tends to be used
to avoid considering the moral dimensions of a decision. Waring
says that the moral value of averting injury, saving life and
ensuring healthy working conditions are ignored in a cost&endash;benefit
analysis. 'The value of safety is its costs and benefits relative
to lost or gained production, possible legal suits, different
groups of workers, and the allocation of scarce resources.' (1988,
p. 20)
Back to Top...
Ignores Distributional Issues
Cost&endash;benefit analysis is about total costs and benefits,
and does not deal with who gets the benefits and who suffers the
costs. As long as the sum of the benefits outweigh the sum of
the costs, even if a small group of people get the benefits and
a whole community suffers the costs, the society as a whole is
assumed to be better off. For example, the building of a third
runway in Sydney will benefit interstate and overseas travellers,
particularly business people who currently suffer from delays
at the airport and who want to arrive at particular times of the
day in order to attend meetings. Some residents also gain if they
are under current flight paths that will have less traffic as
a result of the new runway. But thousands of residents under the
new flight paths will suffer the noise of the extra aircraft traffic.
However, if the benefits in monetary terms outweigh the costs
in monetary terms, then it is assumed that the society will be
better off.
It is sometimes argued by economists that, if the total benefits
outweigh the total costs, the winners could compensate the losers
and still be better off; but this is only theoretical reasoning
and seldom happens. It is also sometimes argued that, although
the distribution of benefits and costs may be unfair in particular
instances, it will all balance out in the end. However, the tendency
in our society is more often for winners to win and losers to
continually lose&emdash;so that poor people are the ones who tend
to suffer the costs of hazardous, dirty or unwelcome developments.
Another distributional issue, mentioned earlier, is that values
based on consumer preferences and the market tend to reflect and
therefore maintain the prevailing distribution of income. Also,
siting a dirty industry in an already dirty area will be less
costly than siting it in a low-pollution area&emdash;because the
costs of pollution, if measured in terms of decline in property
values, will be lower. Similarly, siting the polluting industry
in an area that has depressed property values for other reasons
but is nevertheless unpolluted will also be less costly by this
method than siting it in an affluent area; again, the poor are
disadvantaged.
Back to Top...
Biased against future generations
Normally, future costs and benefits are discounted (reduced)
because it is assumed that they are not worth as much to people
today. The reasoning behind discounting is as follows: if a person
has the choice of receiving a sum of money now or waiting to get
it later, most economists assume that, even if he or she ignores
inflation, the person would prefer to get the money now. He or
she will only be interested in getting it later if the sum has
become larger by then. Pearce, Markandya and Barbier (1991) put
forward the following reasons for this:
- Money obtained now can be invested and earn interest.
- People tend to be impatient.
- The person might die before he or she gets the money.
- One cannot be sure of getting the money in the future.
- People in the future will probably be better off; money will
not be worth as much then.
For the economist, $1 this year is worth $1+r (the discount rate)
next year. Therefore, $1 next year is worth less than $1 this
year; it has to be discounted (reduced) if we are to consider
it in today's values. The procedure for reducing future costs
and benefits to today's values is known as discounting, and the
rate at which costs and benefits are discounted is known as the
discount rate. The ratio of benefits to costs (the benefit: cost
ratio) is worked out by dividing the net present values of benefits
by the net present value of costs. A project generally should
not proceed if costs exceed benefits; that is, where the benefit:
cost ratio is less than one.
Whether a project goes ahead or not will often depend on what
discount rate is used. For example, since economic returns usually
come later than construction costs, the use of a low discount
rate will generally raise the ratio of benefits to direct costs,
and make a project seem more attractive. Small differences in
discount rates can make big differences in the final ratio of
benefits to costs if long-term costs or benefits are being considered.
For example, consider the following:
The net present value of an income or cost of $200 million
in 50 year's time would be
- $ 1.7 million if the discount rate is 10 per cent;
- $ 17 million if the discount rate is 5 per cent;
- $ 74 million if the discount rate is 2 per cent.
Choosing an appropriate discount rate therefore makes a big difference
to the outcomes&emdash;but the choice can be very much influenced
by value judgements, including the judgement about entitlements
of future generations. In terms of environmental costs, the higher
the discount rate that is used, the greater is the bias towards
the present and against the future. The further the costs are
into the future, the less they will be worth in today's values;
yet future generations will still have to put up with them. An
extreme example is that of the storage of radioactive waste, which
can last hundreds of thousands of years into the future. A large
cost arising from this waste hundreds of years hence would be
worth almost nothing in today's values. A more commonplace example
is the case of reafforestation. 'Except at very low discount rates,
a tree that takes 40 years to grow would have a very low value
today to show against its costs.' (ESD Working Group Chairs 1992,
p. 14)
Discounting therefore discriminates against future generations
by saying that future costs are worth less than present costs.
Because costs that are more than thirty years away become almost
valueless using discounting at normal rates, long-term environmental
costs such as resource depletion may be effectively ignored. Yet
the chairs of the ecologically sustainable development working
groups have pointed out that there are practical difficulties
for governments in using discount rates that are lower than market
rates of interest, because it would seem that the government was
getting less return on its money than it could get elsewhere and
that the cost of raising the funds was more than the returns (1992,
p. 16). Nevertheless, as they also pointed out, the community
does accept low rates of return on socially important investments
such as schools and public services (p. 12).
Economist David Pearce says:
There are those who argue that we cannot take account
of costs to generations yet unborn, for to do so is to widen the
concept of 'democratic voting' in an unacceptable way. Those who
are alive at the time of the decision constitute the 'proper'
electorate. Others draw attention to the fact that the kind of
'inter-generational discrimination' implicit in discounting is
an increasing feature of our society. Examples might be the potential
for heating up the atmosphere through continued burning of fossil
fuels ('the greenhouse effect'), nuclear power waste problems,
continued and expanding use of toxic metals and chemicals which
do not degrade in the environment, the use of chlorofluorocarbons
(CFCs) which punch 'holes' in the stratosphere and increase the
amount of ultra-violet rays in certain areas, perhaps inducing
skin cancers, and so on.
It seems fair to say that there is no consensus at all on what
to do about this aspect of CBA. (1983, p. 53)
However, while discounting money may make sense, discounting
environmental values seems to be an example of what Daly and Cobb
(1989, chapter 7) call 'misplaced concreteness': in other words,
getting mixed up between the measure (in this case, money) and
the real world (the environment), and assuming that the real world
behaves as the measure does. Just because people would rather
have money now than later, so they can invest it or to be sure
of having it, this does not mean that they will value the maintenance
of an area of environmental significance less each year into the
future.
In reality, an area of environmental significance is likely to
increase in value as areas like it become scarce and our knowledge
about ecosystems increases. Such areas are also likely to become
more valuable as populations increase and, especially, if leisure
time increases.
The idea that someone would like to consume now rather than in
the future is also not applicable to public goods which can be
enjoyed now and in the future; only consumption that uses up the
environment, such as logging or pollution, fits this model. Society
gets the benefits of environmental preservation, and therefore
the risk of one person dying before he or she gets the benefits
is meaningless.
The operational basis of discounting is that there exists
a concrete process of depositing money in the bank where it grows
at a given rate of interest and this process is viewed as an alternative
to investing one's money in any particular project. In their models
economists seem to consider all good things as equivalent to a
sum of money in the bank, and therefore to expect that good thing,
whatever it is, to grow like money in the bank. But when in their
models economists discount future utility or happiness, then we
are already getting into misplaced concreteness, because there
is no real world operation by which satisfaction today can be
stored in a fund and even if there were, there is no reason to
expect such a fund to grow to give greater satisfaction tomorrow...
The prize for nonsensical discounting must go to those who
discount future fatalities to their 'equivalent' present value
one is left with the suspicion that the motivation underlying
the whole ludicrous calculation is simply to convert a 'very
large number' into a very small number under the cover of numerological
darkness. (Daly & Cobb 1989, pp. 153&endash;4)
Public goods, particularly environmental 'goods', are not like
other types of goods. It is for this reason that they do not normally
have prices attached to them in the first place. There is no reason
to treat them like other goods when it comes to discounting.
Source: Sharon Beder,
The Nature of Sustainable Development,
2nd edition, Scribe, Newham, Vic.,1996.
Back to Top...