The Resource Assessment Commission's economic analysis indicated
that logging should not go ahead in the national estate areas
of the south-east forests. It is because of instances such as
this that environmental economists and some conservationists believe
that if the values of biodiversity protection could be converted
into monetary terms and compared with the benefits of exploiting
those biological resources, policy-makers would be more likely
to make decisions in favour of maintaining biodiversity. It may
be for this reason that the Forestry Commission of NSW dislikes
and avoids cost-benefit analyses.
The question remains, should these economic methods be supported
for the pragmatic reason that it can help the conservationist?
Economic analysis is, of course, a sword that can cut both ways:
it can also favour developments with large environmental impacts
if the profits to be made are also very large. As was noted in
chapter 8, it will usually not be environmentalists who control
how the analysis is done. It is a risky strategy to embrace methods
that make money and species interchangeable.
This approach has also been criticised on several other grounds,
the first being that species can not be valued. This is because
our society is ignorant of most species that exist, the role they
play in their ecosystems, how they interact, and the use or value
they might be to humans now and in the future. David Ehrenfeld,
a US professor of biology, also asks 'How do we deal with values
of organisms whose very existence escapes our notice?' and 'What
sort of value do we assign to the loss to the community when a
whole generation of its children can never experience the streams
in their environment as amenities?' (1988, p. 215).
Those in favour of valuation admit the difficulty of getting
an accurate dollar value, but answer that 'even a partial valuation
in monetary terms of the benefits of conserving biological resources
can provide at least a lower limit to the full range of benefits'.
They are therefore 'important in crystallizing those issues involving
implicit value judgements that may otherwise be ignored' (McNeely
et al. 1990, pp. 26&endash;7).
Ehrenfeld points out that attaching a dollar value to a species
still does not guarantee its survival. He points to a study done
by a mathematician in 1973 which showed that 'it was economically
preferable to kill every blue whale left in the oceans as fast
as possible and reinvest the profits in growth industries rather
than to wait for the species to recover to the point where it
could sustain an annual catch' (1988, p. 213).
Indeed, the Business Council of Australia says 'biological diversity
can yield some unpredictable benefits in the form of new products
or processes at some time in the future' (1991, pp. 6& 7). But
it argues that this value should be measured against the value
of economic developments which reduce biological diversity. For
the council, uncertainty about the impacts of a development on
biological diversity is not a reason for stopping a development.
It says that there is no guarantee in nature that particular species
will survive. Development will in fact provide the money for research
into biodiversity. It is such research that will provide the means
to ensure the survival of threatened species.
In contrast, the major Australian environmental groups argue
that:
Maintenance of the natural environment, including the
conservation of biodiversity and the protection of ecological
integrity, should be a fundamental constraint on all economic
activity. An ecologically sustainable society would adopt an approach
to biodiversity which conserved all species, their genetic diversity
and their habitats
(ed. Hare 1990, p. 7)
They argue that this is necessary for human survival because
'human societies rely on biodiversity to provide food, medicine,
fibres and other resources', and natural ecosystems provide services
such as the assimilation of waste, and the provision of vital
natural resources such as fresh water and a healthy living environment.
Norton uses the argument that biodiversity is necessary for survival
to argue against the placing of dollar values on species so that
they might be weighed against such things as 'the value of real
estate around reservoirs and kilowatt-hours of hydroelectric power'
(1988, p. 204). He compares such reasoning to hospital administrators
trying to work out which parts of a life-support system can be
disconnected and sold to raise money for the hospital. They do
not really know which part is necessary for the continued operation
of the support system, and have to guess which parts will not
be missed.
It is one thing to treat the valuation of biodiversity
as a guessing game or as a set of very interesting theoretical
problems in welfare economics. It is quite another thing to suggest
that the guesses we make are to be the basis of decision making
that will affect the functioning of the ecosystems on which we
and our children will depend for life. (1988, p. 204)
Ehrenfeld (1988) dislikes this argument about needing biodiversity
for human survival. He claims that some of the most loved and
most threatened species can be totally unnecessary for ecological
survival. Such species might include the panda, the condor or
even the koala.
These arguments tend to be human-centred, or anthropocentric.
The idea of valuing species and biodiversity in terms of what
they are worth to humans (the instrumental or utilitarian approach)
has been criticised by those who believe that animals and plants
have an intrinsic value. Deep ecologists, for example, argue that
humans are a part of nature, not separate from and superior to
nature. They argue that all things in the biosphere have an equal
right to live and blossom and reach their full potential. All
plants, animals and organisms have a value in themselves that
is independent of their usefulness to humans. As a result of this
thinking, they believe that humans have no right to reduce the
diversity of life except to satisfy vital needs, such as food
and shelter. (Devall & Sessions 1985, pp. 65& 70)
Nevertheless, it is humans they have to appeal to if biodiversity
is to be preserved. Ehrenfeld argues that conservation of biodiversity
requires changes in public morality. He says that 'the public
must come to understand the inherent wrongness of the destruction
of biological diversity' (1988, p. 215).
Back to top...